Infinitely Powerful Logicians

Time to post the solution to my last problem involving the Axiom of Choice. First off, the mere existence of a solution to this problem should terrify you. The reason is that if only finitely many people are wrong, that means that there is a last person that is wrong. So, if you were to look at the guesses of the logicians, you would find that they have some right and some wrong for a while, but then suddenly there is a last person who is wrong and everybody after that is just magically right, in spite of the fact that those people had no special information. Somehow, they were able to use the infinite hats in front of them to deduce their own hat colour, even though it was independent.

It is also worth saying that in most problems like this, where everybody must guess simultaneously, you try to arrange the peoples guesses so that when something goes wrong, it goes maximally wrong. This is needed because each person on their own has a fixed probability of being wrong, so you simply try to make those fixed probabilities non-independent so that you minimize the chance that things go wrong.

In this problem, each person has a 50% chance of being wrong at the time they make their guess. This is a bit of a problem, as that means that on average half of the people will be wrong and there is very little one can do about it. Fortunately, the Axiom of Choice destroys usual notions of probability. It does this by creating sets of non-defined length. Simply put, length can be defined in terms of the probability that you were to pick an element of the set. Specifically, if you have a subset S of [0,1], and you were to pick an element of [0,1] at random, the probability that you would get an element of S would be L(S), the sets length. If the Axiom of Choice allows for sets with no length, it also allows for sets that we have no well defined probability of picking an element of.

Alright, time to start constructing the solution. Consider the sequence of hats that the logicians are wearing to be an infinite binary sequence, starting from the back of the line (x1, x2, x3...). Use that binary sequence to construct a real number, y, between zero and one, represented in binary as y=0.x1x2x3...

Next, construct an equivalence class on the reals between zero and one. We will consider two real numbers, a and b, to be equivalent if, when expressed in binary, a and b differ in only finitely many decimal places. Now we use the axiom of choice to select one element from each equivalence class and call the set V. So, for all z between zero and one, there is exactly one element of V that differs from z in only finitely many decimal places. Also, no two elements of V differ from eachother in finitely many decimal places. Have the logicians agree on the set V and memorize it.

Now, each logician is to look at the hats in front of them, and they know "most" of the binary sequence of the actual number they are in (calling that y). That is to say, logician number 6 can consider y=0.x1x2x3x4x5x6x7x8x9.... The first 6 digits are unknown to him, but all the rest are known. Every single logician knows all but finitely many of the digits in the binary expansion of y. As a result, every logician is aware of what equivalence class y is in, and they all have agreed on an element in V (call it k) that differs from y in only finitely many places. Thus, if everybody guesses assuming that y actually is k, then only finitely many of them will be wrong.

Naturally, this requires that the logicians be capable of an infinite amount of work, they must find a choice function, then they must memorize all the elements in the set V (or just memorize the choice function, its the same). Next they must examine all of the (infinite) hats in front of them to figure out what equivalence class they are in to select an element of V.

But, if they can do all of that, they can accomplish the rather miraculous task of solving this problem.

It is also worth saying that they can solve this problem even if the hats are not restricted to being white or black. As long as they know the set of colours that the hats can come from, they can do the exact same thing. Instead of considering binary sequences, they simply consider trinary sequences, or hexadecimal, or whatever it takes to get as many digits are there are hat colours. If that doesn't make you think the Axiom of Choice is crazy, I don't know what will.

No comments: